Results for 'Flora I. Matheson'

986 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Ethics of health research with prisoners in Canada.Diego S. Silva, Flora I. Matheson & James V. Lavery - 2017 - BMC Medical Ethics 18 (1):31.
    Despite the growing recognition for the need to improve the health of prisoners in Canada and the need for health research, there has been little discussion of the ethical issues with regards to health research with prisoners in Canada. The purpose of this paper is to encourage a national conversation about what it means to conduct ethically sound health research with prisoners given the current realities of the Canadian system. Lessons from the Canadian system could presumably apply in other jurisdictions. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  8
    Laird's Problem of the Self.Flora I. Mackinnon - 1918 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 15 (20):553.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  6
    Problems of the Self.Flora I. MacKinnon - 1918 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 15 (20):553-557.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  10
    The meaning of "emergent" in Lloyd Morgan's "emergent evolution".Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Mind 33 (131):311-315.
  5.  8
    Behaviorism and metaphysics.Flora I. MacKinnon - 1928 - Journal of Philosophy 25 (13):353-356.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  10
    On paramnesia.Flora I. Mackinnon - 1924 - Mind 33 (131):304-310.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    The doctrine of measure in the philebus.Flora I. Mackinnon - 1925 - Philosophical Review 34 (2):144-153.
  8.  3
    The logical implications of the word "this".Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Journal of Philosophy 21 (7):181-184.
  9.  24
    Pleasure and Behavior. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Journal of Philosophy 21 (20):558-559.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  22
    Enchiridion Ethicum. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon - 1931 - Journal of Philosophy 28 (17):466-470.
  11.  15
    Enchiridion Ethicum.A Sermon, Preached before the House of Commons, March 31, 1647.Biathanatos.Conway Letters, The Correspondence of Anne, Viscountess Conway, Henry More. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon, Henry More, Ralph Cudworth, John Donne, J. William Hebel & Marjorie Hope Nicholson - 1931 - Journal of Philosophy 28 (17):466.
  12.  49
    The Ethics of Hercules. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Journal of Philosophy 21 (15):415-416.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  4
    The Ethics of Hercules. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Journal of Philosophy 21 (15):415-416.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  2
    aird's Problem of the Self. [REVIEW]Flora I. Mackinnon - 1918 - Journal of Philosophy 15 (20):553.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  8
    review of Wells, Pleasure and Behavior. [REVIEW]Flora I. MacKinnon - 1924 - Journal of Philosophy 21 (20):558-559.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  12
    Brown's Rationality.Sonia Ryang, Warren Schmaus, Steven I. Miller, Carl Matheson, Harold Brown, Govindan Parayil, Steven Yearley & Stephen Turner - 1992 - Social Epistemology 6 (1):35-43.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  17
    The Case for Rational Uniqueness.Jonathan Matheson - 2011 - Logic and Episteme 2 (3):359-373.
    The Uniqueness Thesis, or rational uniqueness, claims that a body of evidence severely constrains one’s doxastic options. In particular, it claims that for any body of evidence E and proposition P, E justifies at most one doxastic attitude toward P. In this paper I defend this formulation of the uniqueness thesis and examine the case for its truth. I begin by clarifying my formulation of the Uniqueness Thesis and examining its close relationship to evidentialism. I proceed to give some motivation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  18.  88
    Escaping Heaven.Benjamin Matheson - 2014 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 75 (3):197-206.
    In response to the problem of Hell, Buckareff and Plug (Relig Stud 41:39–54, 2005; Relig Stud 45:63–72, 2009) have recently proposed and defended an ‘escapist’ conception of Hell. In short, they propose that the problem of Hell does not arise because God places an open-door policy on Hell. In this paper, I expose a fundamental problem with this conception of Hell—namely, that if there’s an open door policy on Hell, then there should be one on Heaven too. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19.  17
    A duty of ignorance.David Matheson - 2013 - Episteme 10 (2):193-205.
    Conjoined with the claim that there is a moral right to privacy, each of the major contemporary accounts of privacy implies a duty of ignorance for those against whom the right is held. In this paper I consider and respond to a compelling argument that challenges these accounts (or the claim about a right to privacy) in the light of this implication. A crucial premise of the argument is that we cannot ever be morally obligated to become ignorant of information (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  20
    Are Conciliatory Views of Disagreement Self-Defeating?Jonathan Matheson - 2015 - Social Epistemology 29 (2):145-159.
    Conciliatory views of disagreement are an intuitive class of views on the epistemic significance of disagreement. Such views claim that making conciliation is often required upon discovering that another disagrees with you. One of the chief objections to these views of the epistemic significance of disagreement is that they are self-defeating. Since, there are disagreements about the epistemic significance of disagreement, such views can be turned on themselves, and this has been thought to be problematic. In this paper, I examine (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21.  22
    Unknowableness and Informational Privacy.David Matheson - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Research 32:251-267.
    Despite their differences, the three most prominent accounts of informational privacy on the contemporary scene—the Control Theory, the Limited Access Theory, and the Narrow Ignorance Theory—all hold that an individual’s informational privacy is at least partly a function of a kind of inability of others to know personal facts about her. This common commitment, I argue, renders the accounts vulnerable to compelling counterexamples. I articulate a new account of informational privacy—the Broad Ignorance Theory—that avoids the commitment by rendering an individual’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22. Χóλοσ, μh̃νισ, νεĩκοσ in den argonautika Des apollonios rhodios.Flora Manakidou - 1998 - Philologus: Zeitschrift für Antike Literatur Und Ihre Rezeption 142 (2):241-260.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  10
    How to Be an Epistemic Value Pluralist.David Matheson - 2011 - Dialogue 50 (2):391-405.
    ABSTRACT: In this paper I defend an epistemic value pluralism according to which true belief, justified belief, and knowledge are all fundamental epistemic values. After laying out reasons to reject epistemic value monism in its central forms, I present my pluralist alternative and show how it can adequately explain the greater epistemic value of knowledge over both true belief and justified belief, despite their fundamentality. I conclude with a sketch of how this pluralism might be generalized beyond the epistemic domain (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  19
    Aristotle's Cognitive Science: Belief, Affect and Rationality.Ian Mccready-Flora - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (2):394-435.
    I offer a novel interpretation of Aristotle's psychology and notion of rationality, which draws the line between animal and specifically human cognition. Aristotle distinguishes belief (doxa), a form of rational cognition, from imagining (phantasia), which is shared with non-rational animals. We are, he says, “immediately affected” by beliefs, but respond to imagining “as if we were looking at a picture.” Aristotle's argument has been misunderstood; my interpretation explains and motivates it. Rationality includes a filter that interrupts the pathways between cognition (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  26
    Is there a well-founded solution to the generality problem?Jonathan D. Matheson - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (2):459-468.
    The generality problem is perhaps the most notorious problem for process reliabilism. Several recent responses to the generality problem have claimed that the problem has been unfairly leveled against reliabilists. In particular, these responses have claimed that the generality problem is either (i) just as much of a problem for evidentialists, or (ii) if it is not, then a parallel solution is available to reliabilists. Along these lines, Juan Comesaña has recently proposed solution to the generality problem—well-founded reliabilism. According to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26.  15
    Knowing Persons.David Matheson - 2010 - Dialogue 49 (3):435-453.
    ABSTRACT: There is an intuitive distinction between knowing someone in a detached manner and knowing someone in a more intimate fashion — personally. The latter seems to involve the specially active participation of the person known in a way that the former does not. In this paper I present a novel, communication account of knowing someone personally that successfully explains this participation. The account also illuminates the propositional and testimonial character of the personal knowledge of persons, the conditions of limited (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  17
    The Ethics of Belief: Individual and Social.Rico Vitz & Jonathan Matheson (eds.) - 2014 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    How do people form beliefs, and how should they do so? This book presents seventeen new essays on these questions, drawing together perspectives from philosophy and psychology. The first section explores the ethics of belief from an individualistic framework. It begins by examining the question of doxastic voluntarism-i.e., the extent to which people have control over their beliefs. It then shifts to focusing on the kinds of character that epistemic agents should cultivate, what their epistemic ends ought to be, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. Epistemic Autonomy and Intellectual Humility: Mutually Supporting Virtues.Jonathan Matheson - 2024 - Social Epistemology 38 (3):318-330.
    Recently, more attention has been paid to the nature and value of the intellectual virtue of epistemic autonomy. One underexplored issue concerns how epistemic autonomy is related to other intellectual virtues. Plausibly, epistemic autonomy is closely related to a number of intellectual virtues like curiosity, inquisitiveness, intellectual perseverance, and intellectual courage to name just a few. Here, however, I will examine the relation between epistemic autonomy and intellectual humility. I will argue that epistemic autonomy and intellectual humility bear an interesting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  10
    Consciousness and synchronic identity.Carl Matheson - 1990 - Dialogue 29 (4):523-530.
    The question “What makes a group of simultaneous experiences the experiences of a single person?” has been nearly ignored in the philosophical literature for the past few decades. The most common answer to this much neglected question is “Two simultaneous experiences belong to a single person if there is a common consciousness or awareness of them.” However, consciousness and awareness are difficult concepts to analyze, so that little of substance has been said of the answer. Recently, Oaklander has argued that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  93
    Epistemic Relativism.Jonathan Matheson - 2012 - In Andrew Cullison (ed.), The Continuum Companion to Epistemology. New York: Continuum. pp. 161-179.
    In this paper I examine the case for epistemic relativism focusing on an argument for epistemic relativism formulated (though not endorsed) by Paul Boghossian. Before examining Boghossian’s argument, however, I first examine some preliminary considerations for and against epistemic relativism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  28
    Conciliatory Views of Disagreement and Higher-Order Evidence.Jonathan Matheson - 2009 - Episteme 6 (3):269-279.
    Conciliatory views of disagreement maintain that discovering a particular type of disagreement requires that one make doxastic conciliation. In this paper I give a more formal characterization of such a view. After explaining and motivating this view as the correct view regarding the epistemic significance of disagreement, I proceed to defend it from several objections concerning higher-order evidence (evidence about the character of one's evidence) made by Thomas Kelly (2005).
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  32.  12
    A Distributive Reductionism About the Right to Privacy.David Matheson - 2008 - The Monist 91 (1):108-129.
    Ignorance theorists about privacy hold that it amounts to others’ ignorance of one’s personal information. I argue that ignorance theorists should adopt a distributive reductionist approach to the right to privacy, according to which it is reducible to elements that, despite having something significant in common, are distributed across more fundamental rights to person, liberty, and property. The distributed reductionism that I present carries two important features. First, it is better suited than its competitors to explain a sense of scatter (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Deep Disagreements and Rational Resolution.Jonathan Matheson - 2018 - Topoi (5):1-13.
    The purpose of this paper is to bring together work on disagreement in both epistemology and argumentation theory in a way that will advance the relevant debates. While these literatures can intersect in many ways, I will explore how some of views pertaining to deep disagreements in argumentation theory can act as an objection to a prominent view of the epistemology of disagreement—the Equal Weight View. To do so, I will explain the Equal Weight View of peer disagreement and show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  34.  10
    Is there a hermeneutics of suspicion in being and time?Matheson Russell - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):97 – 118.
    Hubert Dreyfus has claimed that Heidegger's phenomenological method involves a “hermeneutics of suspicion”. This is an intriguing suggestion, and if it were correct it would indicate that the standard interpretations overlook a significant aspect of the methodology of Being and Time. But is there really a hermeneutics of suspicion in Being and Time? Leslie MacAvoy has offered the most sustained challenge to Dreyfus on this point, arguing that his “hermeneutics of suspicion thesis” misconstrues both the overarching project and the methodological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  8
    Protagoras and Plato in Aristotle: Rereading the Measure Doctrine.Ian C. McCready-Flora - 2015 - In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 49. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 71-128.
    We have far less evidence for Aristotle’s reception of Protagoras than we like to think, and the evidence we do have is somewhere we hardly ever look. With one exception, every reference Aristotle makes to the Measure Doctrine—Protagoras’ claim that humans are the ‘measure of all things —concerns the Doctrine as amplified in Plato’s Theaetetus, and the ‘Protagoras’ in question is Plato’s fictional character as fictional. Metaph. I 1, 1053a35–b3 provides the only exception, where Aristotle offers an anomalous reading of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Compatibilism and personal identity.Benjamin Matheson - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (2):317-334.
    Compatibilists disagree over whether there are historical conditions on moral responsibility. Historicists claim there are, whilst structuralists deny this. Historicists motivate their position by claiming to avoid the counter-intuitive implications of structuralism. I do two things in this paper. First, I argue that historicism has just as counter-intuitive implications as structuralism when faced with thought experiments inspired by those found in the personal identity literature. Hence, historicism is not automatically preferable to structuralism. Second, I argue that structuralism is much more (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37. In defence of the Four-Case Argument.Benjamin Matheson - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (7):1963-1982.
    Pereboom’s Four-Case Argument was once considered to be the most powerful of the manipulation arguments against compatibilism. However, because of Demetriou’s :595–617, 2010) response, Pereboom has significantly weakened his argument. Manipulation arguments in general have also been challenged by King : 65–83, 2013). In this paper, I argue that the Four-Case Argument resists both these challenges. One upshot is that Pereboom doesn’t need weaken his argument. Another is that compatibilists still need a response the Four-Case Argument. And another is that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38.  97
    Affect and Sensation: Plato’s Embodied Cognition.Ian McCready-Flora - 2018 - Phronesis 63 (2):117-147.
    _ Source: _Volume 63, Issue 2, pp 117 - 147 I argue that Plato, in the _Timaeus_, draws deep theoretical distinctions between sensation and affect, which comprises pleasure, pain, desire and emotion. Sensation is both ‘fine-grained’ and ‘immediate’. Emotions, by contrast, are mediated and coarse-grained. Pleasure and pain are coarse-grained but, in a range of important cases, immediate. The _Theaetetus_ assimilates affect to sensation in a way the _Timaeus_ does not. Smell frustrates Timaeus because it is coarse-grained, although unlike pleasure (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  77
    Gritty Faith.Jonathan Matheson - 2018 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 92 (3):499-513.
    In this paper, I will connect some of the philosophical research on non-doxastic accounts of faith to some psychological research on grit. In doing so I hope to advance the debate on both the nature and value of faith by connecting some philosophical insights with some empirical grounding. In particular, I will use Duckworth’s research to show that seeing faith as grit both captures the philosophical motivations for non-doxastic accounts of faith and comes with empirical backing that such faith is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  40. Towards a structural ownership condition on moral responsibility.Benjamin Matheson - 2019 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (4):458-480.
    In this paper, I propose and defend a structural ownership condition on moral responsibility. According to the condition I propose, an agent owns a mental item if and only if it is part of or is partly grounded by a coherent set of psychological states. As I discuss, other theorists have proposed or alluded to conditions like psychological coherence, but each proposal is unsatisfactory in some way. My account appeals to narrative explanation to elucidate the relevant sense of psychological coherence.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41. Tracing and heavenly freedom.Benjamin Matheson - 2018 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 84 (1):57-69.
    Accounts of heavenly freedom typically attempt to reconcile the claim that the redeemed have free will with the claim that the redeemed cannot sin. In this paper, I first argue that Pawl and Timpe :396–417, 2009) tracing account of heavenly freedom—according to which the redeemed in heaven have only ‘derivative’ free will—is untenable. I then sketch an alternative account of heavenly freedom, one which eschews derivative free will. On this account, the redeemed are able to sin in heaven.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  13
    Analytic Practical Theory of Education and German Critical Pädagogik: Comparing Their Critical Dimension.Flora Liuying Wei - 2019 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 39 (6):625-640.
    Two critical theories—both contemporaneous and complementary—in Western philosophy of education spanning the 1960s to the 1980s will first be explicated, and then their significant intellectual values will be discussed on the basis of such a comparative account. These two critical models are the practical theory of education in the Anglophone world and the critical theory of education in the Continental Germany. I will introduce them—namely, analytic practical educational theory and German critical pädagogik—one after another, by focusing on their complementary differences, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  9
    Analytic Practical Theory of Education and German Critical Pädagogik: Comparing Their Critical Dimension.Flora Liuying Wei - 2019 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 39 (6):625-640.
    Two critical theories—both contemporaneous and complementary—in Western philosophy of education spanning the 1960s to the 1980s will first be explicated, and then their significant intellectual values will be discussed on the basis of such a comparative account. These two critical models are the practical theory of education in the Anglophone world and the critical theory of education in the Continental Germany. I will introduce them—namely, analytic practical educational theory and German critical pädagogik—one after another, by focusing on their complementary differences, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  12
    Analytic Practical Theory of Education and German Critical Pädagogik: Comparing Their Critical Dimension.Flora Liuying Wei - 2019 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 39 (6):625-640.
    Two critical theories—both contemporaneous and complementary—in Western philosophy of education spanning the 1960s to the 1980s will first be explicated, and then their significant intellectual values will be discussed on the basis of such a comparative account. These two critical models are the practical theory of education in the Anglophone world and the critical theory of education in the Continental Germany. I will introduce them—namely, analytic practical educational theory and German critical pädagogik—one after another, by focusing on their complementary differences, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  6
    Analytic Practical Theory of Education and German Critical Pädagogik: Comparing Their Critical Dimension.Flora Liuying Wei - 2019 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 39 (6):625-640.
    Two critical theories—both contemporaneous and complementary—in Western philosophy of education spanning the 1960s to the 1980s will first be explicated, and then their significant intellectual values will be discussed on the basis of such a comparative account. These two critical models are the practical theory of education in the Anglophone world and the critical theory of education in the Continental Germany. I will introduce them—namely, analytic practical educational theory and German critical pädagogik—one after another, by focusing on their complementary differences, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Why Think for Yourself?Jonathan Matheson - 2022 - Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology:1-19.
    Life is a group project. It takes a village. The same is true of our intellectual lives. Since we are finite cognitive creatures with limited time and resources, any healthy intellectual life requires that we rely quite heavily on others. For nearly any question you want to investigate, there is someone who is in a better epistemic position than you are to determine the answer. For most people, their expertise does not extend far beyond their own personal lives, and even (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47.  2
    Colloquium 5 Commentary on Katz.Ian C. McCready-Flora - 2023 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 37 (1):191-204.
    In this response to Emily Katz’s “Aristotle’s Rejection of Mathematized Metaphysics,” I raise questions about her central interpretive claim that mathematical forms cannot, for Aristotle, appear among first principles of nature. Topics addressed include the notion of priority, especially in the sciences; the relationship between natural change and material realization; and the general nature and scope of mathematical explanations for physical phenomena.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  22
    When Protagoras Made Aristotle His Fitch.Ian McCready-Flora - 2019 - Ancient Philosophy Today 1 (2):171-191.
    While defending the principle of non-contradiction in Metaphysics 4, Aristotle argues that the Measure Doctrine of Protagoras is equivalent to the claim that all contradictions are true; given all appearances are true (as the Protagorean maintains), anytime people disagree we get a true contradiction. This argument seems clearly invalid: nothing guarantees that actual disagreement occurs over every matter of fact. The argument in fact works perfectly, I propose, because the Protagorean view falls prey to a version of Fitch's “paradox” of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Creativity and Meaning in Life.David Matheson - 2016 - Ratio 31 (1):73-87.
    To forestall scepticism about meaning in life as a distinct final value, I sketch a preliminary characterization of meaning as superlative final value in life. I then make the case that this characterization helps us better appreciate a neglected substantive account of meaning, namely, Richard Taylor's creativity account. After laying out the creativity account, I argue that it is not just very compelling, but more compelling under the superlativeness characterization than the most prominent of the recent substantive accounts.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50. Fame and Redemption: On the Moral Dangers of Celebrity Apologies.Benjamin Matheson - 2023 - Journal of Social Philosophy.
    In this paper, I first consider three possible explanations for why celebrities typically apologise publicly and sometimes also include their fans among the targets of their apology. I then identify three moral dangers of celebrity apologies, the third of which arises specifically for fan-targeted apologies, and each of which teaches us important lessons about the practice of celebrity apologies. From these individual lessons, I draw more general lessons about apologies from those with elevated social positions and the powers they are (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 986